Friday, July 19, 2024





























































Philosophizing a Pig's Snout

In 2018 Harvard philosopher Christine Korsgaard published Fellow Creatures, a Kantian argument favoring our moral obligations toward animals. A few years later, her book became the subject of an essay by Peter Godfrey-Smith in Aeon. As a philosopher of science, Godfrey-Smith is known for books on animal minds and consciousness. He’s an accomplished writer, but one struggles to understand what exactly he says and criticisms he makes regarding Korsgaard’s challenging book. While Kant might not be the best philosopher one can muster to advocate for animals, Korsgaard makes strides in the field of animal rights by including him in the discussion, evident by Godfrey-Smith’s reaction. Our purpose here is neither a response to Korsgaard nor a reply to Godfrey-Smith but an opportunity to use these authors to talk about how humans harm animals as objects of means to an end.

Godfrey-Smith starts with a focus on corporate animal agriculture and the question about “what kind of wrongness” might entail in farming animals as human food. Unfortunately, he never seems to answer this implied query as he skirts around utilitarianism to reduce suffering and Kantian ethics regarding respect for others. He admits, as is well known, that Kant was not overtly concerned about animals and focused rather on human moral relationships. Nevertheless, Korsgaard attempts to apply Kantian ethics (moral duty under rational principles) to animals. Korsgaard is well-versed not only in Kant but also in Aristotle, so there could be a virtue component to her ethics. For instance, Kant argues how a bad action, such as harming another, will diminish one’s good character. Moreover, Kant’s categorical imperative calls for unconditional moral obligations, and perhaps that dictum could apply to how we treat animals. The categorical imperative says act as if you will it to be a universal law; and/or, act as if using yourself and others as an end and not as a means.

Yet, whatever the philosophical basis of morality (Schopenhauer found it in compassion), Godfrey-Smith does not buy Korsgaard’s Kantian argument. If not by employing socially moral imperatives, then what are we to do about nonhuman animals? We are surrounded by a diversity of life forms. Initially focused on factory farming, Godfrey-Smith seems more inclined to welfare but not rights. He’d look for ways to reduce suffering although slaughterhouse-doomed animals sit in pens as they are fed antibiotic and hormone laced feed to be fattened as human food. With a bolt to the head or a slice to the jugular vein they are sawed into chunks, cut into pieces, and then packaged for wholesale. Farmed animals are useful, then, since they supply humans with meat, protein. Beans, leafy greens, nuts, and seeds also supply protein, and without harmful fats or additives and with much less environmental degradation. If one can achieve nutritional health without animal slaughter, then why not; but Godfrey-Smith does not exactly make any such statement. Korsgaard admits that it’s difficult to draw human/animal comparisons since both have values of importance for themselves. Animals know what is good for them, and as Korsgaard says, they know/experience good because they know/respond to good/bad. Nonetheless, we have created false values regarding animals as sources of food, entertainment, companions, and subjects for experiments.

Korsgaard tries to focus on the interests of others and how we act with reason on their needs and desires, how we can share some basic, common values. Animals in the wild are capable of making choices about what’s good for them: with whom to mate, what to eat, how to raise young, when to travel, where to nest, how to avoid conflict, etc. Not all of that is instinctual per se; some of these types of choices could be part of their individual brain functions or distinct group mentality. After all, individuals who made successful choices survived to spread their genes in a population; those who made bad choices died off. Taking animals out of the wild, artificially breeding them, and confining them to enclosures, as we’ve done for at least eight thousand years, to become human food renders them literally and figuratively as objects barely capable of choice.

Korsgaard, not so much Godfrey-Smith in his essay, tries to help people understand that our fellow creatures we call “animals” deserve respect for their decision making, including types of reflection (like strategizing by apes or wolves and matriarchal decisions by elephants, our examples). With forced confinement in factory farms, zoos, laboratories, etc., humans have erased an individual animal’s ability to choose. Fortunately, this is not entirely the case with animals rescued from slaughter or retied from laboratories who reside in bona fide sanctuaries. In sum, without any categorical imperative, we have chosen our perceived needs over their lives. Korsgaard sees this fault, but Godfrey-Smith apparently does not – at least in this essay, distracted as he seems by his need to neuter Kantian ethics aligned toward animals.

Granted, for Kant, there is no direct duty to animals, but Korsgaard, like Tom Regan, argues that animals have intrinsic value; there could be, then, an indirect duty. We have a duty toward animals since they are part of society, whether as our food, in zoos and laboratories, as companions, or in the wild (though Godfrey-Smith does not really clarify these distinctions). More specifically, as Korsgaard might say, it’s not that animals are without value and don’t sway us to exert moral obligations for them. Kant would say we have no duty to irrational (i.e., nonhuman) beings. W.D. Ross might jump in and say there’s a difference between duty as something we are to be and something we tend toward. Do we act on the face of duty, or do we try to predict consequences advantageous to ourselves? Kant says we should be motivated by duty and not feelings or consequences. However, good acts motivated by feelings have value; feelings need not be eliminated but should not be the reason to act. For Ross, there’s a difference between actual and ideal duty; one can have bad motives and seem to act rightfully, like a foreign agent infiltrating a democratic government. The conundrum seems to hover around how humans have falsely created a world separate from the flora, fauna, and fungi of nature from which we have evolved. We are the foreign agents.

Kant, too, would argue that actions are more important than theological theories or consequences disregarding a rationally-based moral imperative. Religious or cultural traditions are not a sufficient excuse to harm/eat animals given the many healthy plant options now available to most people worldwide. Given that a society can choose to live in cities, why destroy forests for suburban sprawl? Other examples include choices societies make about travel, consumption of goods, etc. Does one really need a sofa or car with leather seats? Godfrey-Smith himself might ask of such scenarios if any of these actions make sense. Perhaps it does if one advocates extreme capitalism at all costs. Consumerist choices that harm animals and the environment are hardly defensible. At any rate, Godfrey-Smith flatly says he prefers “a society where interference is discouraged.” That libertarian attitude ignoring principles of duty can lead to many harms to many people and to animals; it could also write into stone antiquated ideas, like patriarchy, and olden cultural practices, like butchering lambs on Easter or decapitating chickens during the Yom Kippur Kaporos.

Vague, hypothetical wordplay by Godfrey-Smith trivializes the importance of Korsgaard’s argument. We should be concerned about what others think if it could hurt them and other forms of life: deregulating laws protecting clean water; deregulating laws regarding air pollution; deregulating laws ensuring food safety, etc. That’s not interference but rationally-induced moral norms for the common good. What’s “good” for all is not always relative, as Godfrey-Smith suggests. Death and economic destruction from pollution or a pandemic via zoonotic disease are not relative. Cattle ranchers in the western parts of the U.S. are granted cheap grazing rights on federal land to raise livestock for slaughter when those animals trample and ruin native vegetation. The ranchers are encouraged to kill wildlife that’s in a balanced ecosystem. Who is interfering against whom here? Government funding, grants, subsidies, etc. for corporate polluters – many concentrated feeding operations produce massive water waste and pools of offal – are not interference but the taxpayers’ gift to unwittingly engender ecological harms.

Considering acts and choices as values, any nation has, or could have, a character: will that character be soiled by disrespecting and harming others, the environment, or animals whether wild or domestic? Kant believes that moral character is developed through rational reflection about one’s past mistakes. As Korsgaard might put it, for Kant, autonomy is characterized by one who regulates behavior with moral principles she deems law as part of constructing a normative public self. Some social animals, like primates, wolves, and elephants for example, are capable of self-evaluation in a social context: what to do when with whom understanding different outcomes. Considering the emphasis some philosophers place on the rational mind, not discounting a moral sense, we’d have to ask what type of country do citizens envision for themselves in a global environment. Harms against nature, upon reflection and given the climate crisis, are not rational and do not seem to fit Kant’s categorical imperative that asks reasonable people to be like legislators in a world of ends.

Only in rare instances – unprovoked warlike violence – is killing viewed by many as valuable moral aggression. In his criticism of Korsgaard, Godfrey-Smith does not use concrete examples but speaks in vagaries about “ordinary decisions” and veers far away from the core of Korsgaard’s argument: respect for animals, which implies the greater sphere of the natural environment. For instance, he asks, without stating who or what, why we should have “respect for the goals of others”? For the animals? For those advocating for animals? Even those questions can be more specific. For example, should one who protests the transportation to slaughter of pigs hungry and crying in a hot truck be arrested? Would no one respect how that individual person values life? What about the mountain vacation lake used by privileged people over the spring and summer for boating and swimming. The water has become filmy with algae. Factory manufactured chemicals can eliminate the natural growth. Regardless, these chemicals will likely kill the geese, ducks, herons and other species who rely on the lake for sustenance – an ecosystem will perish.

To use Godfrey-Smith’s words, what in this morally-tinged situation is “factual, emotive, structural”? In answer, people might contemplate not using alternative facts or selfish desires in satisfying their recreational needs over wildlife. Godfrey-Smith brushes against an anthropocentric attitude: he does not see how the systems of Gaia that regulate atmospheric and planetary health are on par with human decisions about environmental regulation, which he fears can become “subversive.” We are animals; that’s a biological fact, evident in harvesting pig organs for human transplant, so there’s genetic parity with us. There’s little moral value in that equation, though, for the pig. Every inch of the pig is harvested, and if not eaten by humans, the snouts become dog chews. A healthy pig would not choose to relinquish her organs and die as a dog’s play chew. What’s subversive is the turning upside down of moral judgment to satisfy human needs and desires over an animal’s ability to live freely. Extending Godfrey-Smith’s thinking to wildlife, humans can then drill, mine, and develop oceans and lands since it’s their prerogative. While Godfrey-Smith uses terms like moral and ethical, he’s unknowingly talking about cultural evolution. We are not really evolving biologically, but we are evolving culturally. Cultural change can be rapid, viz political revolutions in some countries over the past few hundred years. Cultural transformation is also subject to gradual Darwinian selection. One prediction is that given time, the libertarian attitudes espoused by Godfrey-Smith, unless one misreads him – leave me alone to do what I want – are slated to be replaced by more liberal, tolerant, and fair values discussed by John Rawls. The question is whether or not liberal toleration and fair treatment will include animal lives.

Finally, at the end of long digressions, Godfrey-Smith comes back to the animals but succumbs to welfare over rights. Shockingly, he says we have “unique human powers” over our animal kin. We cannot fly, live unaided under water, scale buildings, or burrow and live underground, etc. Of course, we have power in machines, but look how they’ve treated ecological systems. With great limitations, he gets to what he calls cases of “special status,” but then mentions none other than using the phraseology “some kinds of mistreatment.” Factory farming? He seems to suggest smaller, what some might erroneously label “humane” farms, though he’s not explicit. He wavers, too, on the question of sentience positing it as “borderline forms and by degree.” That’s obvious given species evolution, so too with sapience, but it exists in many forms no matter how much (or how little he’d argue). Animals know how to survive in a forest; most “civilized” humans do not. Humans do not have more value if they destroy the environment that wildlife, flora, and fungi have created and conserve. Godfrey-Smith does not address that issue, or others outlined here, though he begs the questions. Instead, he ends with the ambiguous and not novel idea that we need to “rethink our relationships” with the nonhuman world. That’s not a very proactive stance and flies against what Korsgaard, to her credit, tries to establish while Godfrey-Smith attempts to dismantle her efforts.

Being human is not, as Godfrey-Smith suggests, a badge of honor. In her book, Korsgaard has an entire chapter called “The Case Against Human Superiority,” mostly because she sees how animals are important not in the grand evolutionary scheme but to their kin, other species, and even humans. That’s a good start, as Korsgaard ultimately disagrees with Kant’s belief that only humans have moral standing. She goes on to say how some humans argue there’s no duty to animals without any reciprocal relationship; but we live in a world filled with the beauty, sounds, and antics of animals to whom we are indubitably connected via biophilia, evolutionary kinship, and their ecosystem engineering. With compassion we are able to value an animal’s life, but not all people are equally compassionate.  Even so, Schopenhauer might say, if we have obligations and duties as rational, moral and somewhat egoistic beings, we should be concerned about the differing conditions of various life forms without only heeding an a priori hypothetical imperative.

Gregory F. Tague, Ph.D. and Fredericka A. Jacks

Bibliography of Works Consulted

Alvaro, Carlo. 2019. Ethical Veganism, Virtue Ethics, and the Great Soul. Lanham: Lexington Books.

Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2021. “Philosophers and Other Animals.” Aeon, 25 February. 

Kant, Immanuel. 1797. The Metaphysics of Morals. Mary Gregor, trans. Cambridge: CUP, 1996.

Korsgaard, Christine. 2018. Fellow Creatures: Our Obligations to Other Animals. Oxford: Oxford U.P.

Kuehn, Manfred. 2001. Kant: A Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge U.P.

Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Revised edition. Cambridge, MA: Belknap P. of Harvard U.P.

Regan, Tom. 2004. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: U. of California P.

Ross, W.D. 1930. “The Right and the Good” chapter 2. Ethics: The Classic Readings. David E. Cooper, ed. Oxford: Blackwell, 1998. 246-261.

Schopenhauer, Arthur. 1840. On the Basis of Morality. E.F.J. Payne, trans. Providence, RI: Berghahn Books, 1995.

 

Copyright©2024 by Gregory F. Tague. All Rights Reserved. Image by Pexels from Pixabay

Thursday, May 2, 2024

The New York Declaration on Animal Consciousness


The NY Declaration on Animal Consciousness was announced on 19 April 2024 at New York University. Although the Declaration does not assert certainty in consciousness across all species there is strong support for the claim and therefore a call to consider consciousness when making policy decisions regarding animals. While some might say that any announcement about animal consciousness is not news or might shrug off the “realistic possibility” of consciousness in, for example, fish, the Declaration has wide-ranging implications in areas of teaching, medical research, suburban and rural development, wildlife conservation, etc.

For instance, while many of the signatories are research scientists, what care is henceforth required for “animals” used in experiments? Should animals be excluded from lab experiments, given computer generated imaging and other forms of visual effects and artificial intelligence? Should animal experiments that simply replicate known results cease? Beyond the university lab, what about animals, from mice to monkeys, used in experiments for the corporate beauty, pharmaceutical, or medical industries? What happens to businesses that breed animals simply for the purpose of sale as human food or research bodies in labs? At the conference, one audience member inquired about the fate of animals at the close of an experiment. The person who answered the question, and a primary signatory to the Declaration, said she does not dispose of animals when an experiment is done; but that begs the question about practices of “euthanasia” among other scientists. If you stop and look around, you will realize how animals are ingrained into our lives as pets, companions, workers, food, or objects of entertainment. So, the crystallization of meaning in the Declaration boils down to how we treat the lives of others.

The original 40 signatories don’t call for animal rights but “welfare,” which implies that animals can be used “humanely” for our use. Should animals be objects of experimentation in the first place? Activists would object to the welfare reference and insist on animal rights. The presentation at the start of the conference made clear that among the 40 primary signatories there was discussion and disagreement, so it’s likely that some lean more to rights while others rest on welfare. That’s not a criticism but a reflection of the reality about how animals are currently viewed. Though a declaration, much of the language admits “uncertainty” (as of now) and opens with a question about which animals have a “capacity” for consciousness. To their credit, the signatories imply that many organisms including fish have such a capacity in various degrees based on their evolutionary adaptations. Clearly then, the Declaration is an important development and tool for researchers and animal activists alike. For example, in advancing concerns about welfare or rights, many people can raise legitimate claims about how animals are treated with reference to this document.

The statement of animal consciousness is brief but includes background material, which highlights (in simplified form here) how crows can learn, octopuses evade pain, cuttlefish have memories, cleaner wrasse fish can identify themselves, bees engage in free play, etc. The point is that a consensus of leaders in this arena of inquiry, from scientists to philosophers, confirm that more species have subjective awareness than has been recognized heretofore. Ongoing evidence firmly suggests that more animals have phenomenal consciousness or sentience exhibited in a range of behaviors, from self-consciousness, problem solving, planning, etc. This evidence, so far based on different species, posits a range of “more likely” to the “realistic possibility” and “strong scientific support” of consciousness across a broad range of species.

However one thinks, the New York Declaration on Animal Consciousness is yet another important step forward regarding how humans interact with the living world. Assuming our human ethics of caring, animal rights are linked with human rights, so this pronouncement is a crucial development in establishing rights for all living organisms. To bolster the authority and credibility of the Declaration, the announcement has been covered by many outlets large and small, from Nature News to The Hill

For academic references used by the writers of the New York Declaration, go HERE

The New York Declaration comes almost twelve years after the Cambridge Declaration of Consciousness, HERE

Readers might also be interested in the PETA argument for animal sentience and emotions, HERE

There’s also a declaration of animal personhood by the University of Toulon, France, HERE

Additional resources for the curious can be found on the Literary Veganism site, HERE

-Gregory F. Tague, Ph.D. and Fredericka A. Jacks