Tone Roald. The Subject of Aesthetics: A Psychology of
Art and Experience. Leiden: Brill, 2015. Paper. 174 pages. $57US. ISBN: 978-9004308718.
Alva Noë. Strange Tools: Art and Human Nature. NY: Hill and Wang, 2015.
Hardcover. 287 pages. $28US. ISBN: 978-0809089178.
These two books examine the question of
artistic behavior and especially the nature of our human experience of art.
Drawing from Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Truth
and Method, Tone Roald proposes that knowledge of and understanding in art
culture is part of a historical tradition separate from truth claims made in
the natural sciences. Alva Noë takes a similar stance, arguing that while
evolutionary studies and neuroscience are part of the conversation about art
culture, personal experience and context weigh more in appreciating and
understanding the nature of art. While Roald is interested in the psychological
dimensions of a persistent art experience, Noë is clear that any aesthetic
experience cannot be limited to brain activity. When we talk about artwork, as
far as both authors are concerned, we need to accommodate the wider realm of
the thinking viewer’s engagement with art as it occurs in a world of other
people. However, whereas Roald treats the aesthetic experience on a personal
level, Noë finds the experience of art engaging a range of personal and
cultural ideas.
Relying on Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception, Roald
asserts that empirical descriptions of art experience are more valuable than
classifications or abstractions from philosophers. Indeed, a large part of her
book reports on and discusses interviews Roald conducted with a number of
people and their encounters with paintings and sculpture over the course of
time. In 1986 Arthur Danto famously said that we have reached the end of art since it does not make
anything happen. If that were so, why would we still create and participate in
art? Roald steers away from a philosophical exercise of abstracting art and
instead offers a project where art gives meaning in life.
Well versed in the history of
aesthetics and the philosophy of art (from Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten to
Martin Seel), Roald looks at the psychology of one’s encounter with art and
tries to find what the aesthetic signifies. The title of her book is
deliberately misleading – the subject of aesthetics is not necessarily in the
artwork, certainly not in some philosophical idea, but is the viewer herself. Indeed,
moving away from the “transcendental ego” of Edmund Husserl, Roald following
Merleau-Ponty will emphasize “phenomenological descriptions of the personal in
encounters with art, and not social, economic, or historical explanations” (22).
This approach pretty much goes against Immanuel Kant and his transcendental,
metaphysical aesthetics, his notion of disinterested, cognitive contemplation.
Over the rational philosopher who does not allow for ambiguity, a
phenomenologist like Merleau-Ponty puts the perceiving subject of artwork in
the world, since the sediments of experience in one’s body are crucial in any
meeting with art.
While at times dense, the early
chapters in Roald’s book offer a comprehensive history of aesthetics,
phenomenology of art, and psychological aesthetics. Here, Roald is capable of
interpreting and explaining some complex ideas from John Dewey, Lev Vygotsky, V.S.
Ramachandran and William Hirstein, Semir Zeki, Kurt Koffka, Sigmund Freud,
Georg W.F. Hegel, and Martin Heidegger (as well as those previously mentioned).
Roald suggests that on the subject of aesthetics, philosophy is inadequate in
comparison with psychology. This attitude does not exactly coincide with Alva
Noë’s. For Roald, in line with Gadamer, the arts and humanities are not
precisely scientifically legitimate
but as an alternative investigate human questions in cultural contexts. This
thinking is what led Roald to conduct twenty-five interviews to gather and
explain data on different people’s art experiences in chapter four, “Stories of
Art.”
These fascinating stories of how works
of art can penetrate someone’s life are central to Roald’s book, since she
seeks to “give form and meaning to aesthetic experience” (99), and especially
how one’s experience with art can develop over an extended period of time – in
sharp contrast to Kant who finds the aesthetic experience in one’s first
encounter. Roald develops this chapter from the thinking of Hans Robert Jauss.
First, there is an initial aesthetic reading; second there in a retrospective
interpretation; third, there is a historical reading. Rather than the work of
art as being the constant, “it is the most significant experience that is
investigated...” (100), especially the moment when there is subject-object
ambiguity. I found this chapter compelling, easy to read, and helpful in my own
understanding about art and aesthetics.
In the end, Roald talks about art as
what she terms intrapellation: “The participants...incorporate the work of art
into their subjectivity, wherein the aesthetic experience becomes a background
tone or color...” (131). Of course much of this might depend on the person, and
the person’s proclivities to view certain art; that which resonates with an
individual might be something she was drawn to (even unconsciously) in the
first place. In this way, intrapellation or cognitive perception of the subject
is “a projection of feelings and imaginings onto the work of art...” – while
art is outside one’s body it somehow supports and yet challenges what’s inside
one’s psyche.
▬
Alva Noë’s wide-ranging analysis of engagement
with art is not distant from Tone Roald’s. He too (at time drawing from Dewey
or Merleau-Ponty) emphasizes the individual in the world. The aesthetic
experience is not brain activity per se; rather, the aesthetic experience
depends upon the whole person’s biography, social history, intelligence, and
environment. But over Roald, Noë perceptively makes a connection between art
and philosophy – how both are a means for us to question who we are and what we
do. That is why art is, as Noë proclaims, a strange tool, for it forces us to ask
how we are organized and then pushes us to consider how to reorganize our
literal and figurative vision. The implication is that the manner in which we
see impacts on our ability to function in the world. Noë can rightfully say
that art is like philosophy since the two practices bring shape and
organization to what is not in clear view.
What is refreshing about this book is
how Noë brings art back to the humanities and away from its current
preoccupation with scientists, notably neuroscientists. While an fMRI can
indeed measure hot areas in the brain, there is no telling what the outcome
will be. Like Roald, Noë suggests that art is or can be an extension of one’s
mind – awareness and behavior cannot be fully accounted for by a machine. Not
to be reductive, but art can function like an implement to help achieve what we
might be thinking. In some respects thought is not just in our heads but also
in objects. Or, more precisely, art displaces what we assume we know and
therefore makes us reconceive people, places, and events. While his focus is on
the visual, Noë also ably covers writing (with a perceptive reading of a poem
by Walt Whitman) and music. Writing, too, is a tool: it is not merely to
register items and happenings but a means for us to contemplate, to pose
questions, and to engage with problems.
In chatty and colloquial prose that
tends to wander, the book at times wavers from its focus. For instance, Noë is
dubious of any evolutionary explanation of art and very critical of
neuroscientific explanations of the aesthetic experience. While he makes a nod
to biology and anthropology and acknowledges the naturalness of art, he says we
are predominantly cultural. The question, though, is where in his discussion
does he address the evolutionary biology of culture? He admits that culture is
not simply dropped upon us. Surely – we evolved culture. If one is going to
bring up evolutionary or neuro-biological areas (Roald does not), one should
treat them rather fully. For example, I do not see any timeline or chronology
here, much less any discussion of prehistoric artifacts. So one can dismiss
evolutionary perspectives, but what precisely is being dismissed? While there
is passing mention of cave art (earlier in the book), I see nothing specific
about the dating differences between Lascaux and Chauvet (work by Genevieve von
Petzinger), and there is no mention of rock art. Needless to say, there is no talk
of the many authors who have worked in these areas – Steven Mithen, Sally McBrearty
and Alison Brooks, April Nowell, to name only a few who have actually
discovered and discuss prehistoric artifacts related to the evolution of art.
Evolutionary approaches must deal not
just with the past, but with prehistory – going all the way back – and must
make mention of studies in comparative primatology and Hunter-Gatherer
societies. I don’t see that here. At this point in our history some aspects of
art behavior are purely cultural – what to make as “art” and where to include (view)
it. But underlying any cultural capacities are fitness-enhancing mechanisms for
the individual to survive in a group. These are aspects of what Ellen Dissanayake
recently calls artification, e.g., objects
as part of social rituals. In any case, Dissanayake’s adaptive notions of artification
as well as her earlier view of making special are much less prevalent today
since, in our societies for many hundreds of years, survival as our prehistoric
ancestors grappled with it is not as difficult. There is some discussion of
Dissanayake, who gets treated badly in my opinion (and where Noë relies only on
her earlier idea of making special). No
one theory of evolutionary adaptations will make full account of art behavior,
and even Darwin knew that. The evolutionary psychologist Geoffrey Miller, who
banks everything on sexual selection is also considered (where is Denis Dutton
in Noë’s discussion?), and he has been criticized for leaving out chronology
and reference to artifacts. Indeed, a more thorough response to Miller has been
offered by Kathryn Coe’s The Ancestress
Hypothesis, not referenced.
I find it telling that Noë pretty much relies
on Stephen Davies (a philosopher) who does not ascribe to art as truly adaptive
and who is reluctant to buy into aesthetic sensibilities as continuous in human
beings and other species (and therefore light on sexual selection). However, he
does argue with Davies who talks about perceptual seeing in animals; Noë says
that there is too wide a gulf between mere perception and aesthetic seeing. But
there is no charting here as to how we arrived at aesthetic seeing: it had to
evolve from something somewhere, as even Darwin knew. The neural leap
hypothesis has been questioned, so that’s not the answer. Aesthetic seeing
could not have been inborn in humanity – that’s creationist. Noë says: “it is
highly unlikely that aesthetic seeing would confer enhanced fitness on those capable
of exercising it” (55). A cultural anthropologist might disagree, citing the
social benefits and prestige one could gain in a group.
This account does not consider the
prehistory of what we now call art. As in his chapter on writing, Noë might be
focusing too much on what is high art and not on the prehistoric material
culture that gave rise to what we not call art.
I’d not even raise this point were it not for a chapter that has the word evolution in it and a book that has as
part of its subtitle human nature.
Noë says art (on the same page he references paintings) is “revelation, transformation, reorganization...” (64).
Few would argue with this assertion, but from an evolutionary standpoint –
variation, competition, and inheritance – it took a long time in human history
to arrive at paintings.
Noë spends lots of time on Western art
of the past five hundred years or so. Where is the discussion of ochre (used at
least 300,000 years ago) and body painting, bead making and sharing (even among
Neanderthals), or even stone tools (which get scant treatment) from over one
million years ago? Although we are, in the words of Terrence Deacon, a symbolic
species, artistic traits didn’t just suddenly appear. One could say that art
behaviors are a byproduct of cognition (as Davies and others, like Pinker, suggest).
Okay, but does that then mean that all aspects of, say, intelligence are
byproducts? We did not just evolve one capacity called Intelligence but many
traits we lump under intelligence, including reason, comprehension,
understanding, and judgment. This is where evolutionary psychologists such as
Leda Cosmides and John Tooby have been instructive. It’s not fitness that
survives: adaptive traits and characteristics that contribute to survival and
reproduction, no matter how small but which get passed on, survive. At any
rate, I am happy to see that Noë does consider and discuss the work of Richard
Prum and how the taste for color and sound can evolve with the evolution of the
colors and sounds themselves.
Nevertheless, don’t misread what I say.
Chapter five on art and evolution is useful in that it helps evolutionists
think harder about adaptive claims in relation to the arts. I think there’s
room at the table for all of these disciplines (from philosophy to
neuroscience) to contribute to our understanding of the arts and humanities.
While Noë is correct, now, to say that art is not just about arousing feelings,
that might not have been true early on when it was not yet art and it might
have been a signal (affection), then a sign (family), then a symbol (group). Prum
is not the only biologist to discuss gene/culture co-evolution in this regard.
As one instance, I see no mention of the work by the team of Peter Richerson
and Robert Boyd.
Noë’s book is immensely valuable, has
had a tremendous impact on me, and has actually brought me back to some of my
philosophical roots. I just think that if you are going to raise an objection,
you should cover it more thoroughly. Noë does, however, cover neuroscience and
art more completely, though here too he is a bit hard on pioneers in the area,
like Semir Zeki. While one might disagree with his quibbles about art and
evolution (with such thin coverage), it’s hard to disagree with what he
concludes about art and neuroscience. For example, what Noë says about context
is vital: we need art history to understand art; the arts have meaning and
significance only in a cultural perspective. Importantly, Noë admits that
culture can change the genome and that culture might have organized parts of the brain (60). Culture and biology are
connected. Of course there is a whole theory about the evolution of culture, especially
in its so-called particulate elements, but I see no mention of that, either (authors
such as social psychologist Roy Baumeister, evolutionary psychologist Alex
Mesoudi, and biologist Mark Pagel).
So where does this leave us. Noë is not
a reductive materialist. Like David Chalmers he believes that science will not
and cannot answer everything. Science has its limits (though most scientists I
know might agree with this evaluation). Art cannot be reduced to natural
sensibilities, since what we label as aesthetic sense covers a wide spectrum.
As Noë says: “Art investigates the aesthetic” (71), which in turn makes art
philosophical. At this point, Noë begins a launch against neuroscientific
approaches to understanding art, and this part of the discussion helps
illuminate much of what has come before. Visual perception (even consciousness)
is not, according to Noë, reducible to brain activity. Nonetheless, even
cognitive mechanisms are most likely adaptive, and I don’t see any recognition of
that here. At any rate, Noë is on point to assert that an aesthetic experience
occurs not just in our brain but outside of it – in a social environment. You
can see why I now include Tone Roald and Alva Noë together – there is some curious
overlap. As Noë so nicely puts it, recalling Ludwig Wittgenstein’s dictum that
we are not minds trapped in bodies, art offers the “opportunity to catch
ourselves in the act of encountering the world...” (80).
Many neuroscientists, according to Noë,
claim that the brain in us is what thinks. (An obvious exception would include
Francisco Varela.) But the value of Noë’s book is in reminding us that while
the brain indeed performs work, it is the whole person, her history and
circumstances, who thinks and feels in relation to artworks. Art does not
simply exist to elicit a response; art arouses in us complex thought processes
and the ability for us to put our consciousness in the artwork and outside of
it. Importantly, though, Noë remarks that our visual perception of the world
and art involves the effort of our intelligence in a historically cultural
context. Rather than treating the perception of art as a bodily function, we
need to consider an aesthetic experience as a means to study the people,
places, and events of the world. Perhaps summing up Noë’s thinking is John
Dewey, who says “Artists don’t make things. They make experiences” (205).
The value in these books by Tone Roald
and Alva Noë is great. While it might sound cliché, I found Roald’s book
interesting and Noë’s book challenging. Roald proposes a new method of
evaluating art experience by employing the reception theory of Jauss; Noë unnerves
us to reconsider how art is a resource for new ways of thinking about and
organizing our lives. Even if you know quite a bit about art behavior and
aesthetics, these authors will ask for a reconsideration of the priority of your
ideas. That is, both authors emphasize less the work of art and emphasize more
the outcome of viewing art, the broader parameters of the art experience. The
subject of the aesthetic experience (or of art itself) is not narrowly defined
by historical subjects; the aesthetic experience is akin to the practice of philosophy
and its method of trying to know, of questioning knowledge itself.
-
Gregory F. Tague, Ph.D. Editor ASEBL and author of Art and Adaptation.
Copyright©2016
Gregory F. Tague – All Rights Reserved